2023-05-13 12:59:28 +00:00
|
|
|
\documentclass{report}
|
|
|
|
|
2023-05-18 20:04:20 +00:00
|
|
|
\input{../../preamble}
|
2023-08-10 17:31:14 +00:00
|
|
|
\makecode{../..}
|
2023-05-13 12:59:28 +00:00
|
|
|
|
2023-08-14 19:45:14 +00:00
|
|
|
\externaldocument[S:]{Set}
|
|
|
|
|
2023-05-13 12:59:28 +00:00
|
|
|
\begin{document}
|
|
|
|
|
2023-05-18 18:39:36 +00:00
|
|
|
\header{A Mathematical Introduction to Logic}{Herbert B. Enderton}
|
2023-05-13 12:59:28 +00:00
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\tableofcontents
|
|
|
|
|
2023-05-18 18:39:36 +00:00
|
|
|
\begingroup
|
2023-05-18 19:03:59 +00:00
|
|
|
\renewcommand\thechapter{R}
|
2023-05-18 18:39:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
2023-05-18 19:03:59 +00:00
|
|
|
\chapter{Reference}%
|
2023-07-12 16:54:35 +00:00
|
|
|
\hyperlabel{chap:reference}
|
2023-05-18 18:39:36 +00:00
|
|
|
|
2023-08-08 20:50:48 +00:00
|
|
|
\section{\defined{Construction Sequence}}%
|
|
|
|
\hyperlabel{ref:construction-sequence}
|
|
|
|
|
2023-08-13 18:39:50 +00:00
|
|
|
A \textbf{construction sequence} is a \nameref{ref:finite-sequence}
|
|
|
|
$\ltuple{\epsilon_1}{\epsilon_n}$ of \nameref{ref:expression}s such that for
|
|
|
|
each $i \leq n$ we have at least one of
|
2023-08-09 13:39:41 +00:00
|
|
|
\begin{align*}
|
|
|
|
& \epsilon_i \text{ is a sentence symbol} \\
|
|
|
|
& \epsilon_i = \mathcal{E}_\neg(\epsilon_j) \text{ for some } j < i \\
|
|
|
|
& \epsilon_i = \mathcal{E}_\square(\epsilon_j, \epsilon_k)
|
|
|
|
\text{ for some } j < i, k < i
|
|
|
|
\end{align*}
|
|
|
|
where $\square$ is one of the binary connectives $\land$, $\lor$,
|
|
|
|
$\Rightarrow$, $\Leftrightarrow$.
|
2023-08-08 20:50:48 +00:00
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\section{\defined{Expression}}%
|
|
|
|
\hyperlabel{ref:expression}
|
|
|
|
|
2023-08-13 18:39:50 +00:00
|
|
|
An \textbf{expression} is a \nameref{ref:finite-sequence} of symbols.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\section{\defined{Finite Sequence}}%
|
|
|
|
\hyperlabel{ref:finite-sequence}
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
$S$ is a \textbf{finite sequence} (or \textbf{string}) of members of set $A$
|
|
|
|
if and only if, for some positive integer $n$, we have
|
|
|
|
$S = \ltuple{x_1}{x_n}$, where each $x_i \in A$.
|
2023-08-08 20:50:48 +00:00
|
|
|
|
2023-08-14 19:45:14 +00:00
|
|
|
\section{\defined{Formula-Building Operations}}%
|
|
|
|
\hyperlabel{ref:formula-building-operations}
|
2023-08-08 20:50:48 +00:00
|
|
|
|
2023-08-14 19:45:14 +00:00
|
|
|
The \textbf{formula-building operations} (on expressions) are defined by the
|
|
|
|
equations:
|
2023-08-09 13:39:41 +00:00
|
|
|
\begin{align*}
|
|
|
|
\mathcal{E}_{\neg}(\alpha)
|
|
|
|
& = (\neg \alpha) \\
|
|
|
|
\mathcal{E}_{\land}(\alpha, \beta)
|
|
|
|
& = (\alpha \land \beta) \\
|
|
|
|
\mathcal{E}_{\lor}(\alpha, \beta)
|
|
|
|
& = (\alpha \lor \beta) \\
|
|
|
|
\mathcal{E}_{\Rightarrow}(\alpha, \beta)
|
|
|
|
& = (\alpha \Rightarrow \beta) \\
|
|
|
|
\mathcal{E}_{\Leftrightarrow}(\alpha, \beta)
|
|
|
|
& = (\alpha \Leftrightarrow \beta)
|
|
|
|
\end{align*}
|
2023-08-08 20:50:48 +00:00
|
|
|
|
2023-08-15 02:37:09 +00:00
|
|
|
\code*{Bookshelf/Enderton/Logic/Chapter\_1}
|
2023-08-15 21:04:55 +00:00
|
|
|
{Enderton.Logic.Chapter\_1.Wff}
|
2023-08-14 19:45:14 +00:00
|
|
|
|
2023-08-15 02:37:09 +00:00
|
|
|
\lean{Init/Prelude}
|
|
|
|
{Not}
|
2023-08-14 19:45:14 +00:00
|
|
|
|
2023-08-15 02:37:09 +00:00
|
|
|
\lean{Init/Prelude}
|
|
|
|
{And}
|
2023-08-14 19:45:14 +00:00
|
|
|
|
2023-08-15 02:37:09 +00:00
|
|
|
\lean{Init/Prelude}
|
|
|
|
{Or}
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\lean{Init/Core}
|
|
|
|
{Iff}
|
2023-08-14 19:45:14 +00:00
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\section{\defined{\texorpdfstring{$n$}{n}-tuple}}%
|
|
|
|
\hyperlabel{ref:n-tuple}
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
An \textbf{$n$-tuple} is recursively defined as
|
|
|
|
$$\ltuple{x_1}{x_{n+1}} = \tuple{\ltuple{x_1}{x_n}, x_{n+1}}$$
|
|
|
|
for $n > 1$.
|
|
|
|
We also define $\tuple{x} = x$.
|
|
|
|
|
2023-08-15 02:37:09 +00:00
|
|
|
\lean*{Init/Prelude}
|
|
|
|
{Prod}
|
2023-08-14 19:45:14 +00:00
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\section{\defined{Well-Formed Formula}}%
|
|
|
|
\hyperlabel{ref:well-formed-formula}
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
A \textbf{well-formed formula} (wff) is an \nameref{ref:expression} that can
|
|
|
|
be built up from the sentence symbols by applying some finite number of
|
|
|
|
times the \nameref{ref:formula-building-operations}.
|
|
|
|
|
2023-08-15 02:37:09 +00:00
|
|
|
\code*{Bookshelf/Enderton/Logic/Chapter\_1}
|
2023-08-15 21:04:55 +00:00
|
|
|
{Enderton.Logic.Chapter\_1.Wff}
|
2023-08-15 02:37:09 +00:00
|
|
|
|
2023-05-18 18:39:36 +00:00
|
|
|
\endgroup
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
% Reset counter to mirror Enderton's book.
|
2023-05-13 12:59:28 +00:00
|
|
|
\setcounter{chapter}{0}
|
|
|
|
\addtocounter{chapter}{-1}
|
|
|
|
\chapter{Useful Facts About Sets}%
|
2023-07-12 16:54:35 +00:00
|
|
|
\hyperlabel{chap:useful-facts-about-sets}
|
2023-05-13 12:59:28 +00:00
|
|
|
|
2023-08-13 16:03:41 +00:00
|
|
|
\section{\unverified{Lemma 0A}}%
|
2023-07-12 16:54:35 +00:00
|
|
|
\hyperlabel{sec:lemma-0a}
|
2023-05-13 12:59:28 +00:00
|
|
|
|
2023-08-09 13:39:41 +00:00
|
|
|
\begin{lemma}[0A]
|
2023-08-13 16:03:41 +00:00
|
|
|
Assume that $\ltuple{x_1}{x_m} = \ltuple{y_1, \ldots, y_m}{y_{m+k}}$.
|
|
|
|
Then $x_1 = \ltuple{y_1}{y_{k+1}}$.
|
2023-08-09 13:39:41 +00:00
|
|
|
\end{lemma}
|
2023-08-08 20:50:48 +00:00
|
|
|
|
2023-08-09 13:39:41 +00:00
|
|
|
\begin{proof}
|
2023-08-13 16:03:41 +00:00
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
For natural number $m$, let $P(m)$ be the statement:
|
2023-08-13 18:39:50 +00:00
|
|
|
\begin{induction}
|
|
|
|
\hyperlabel{sec:lemma-0a-ih}
|
|
|
|
If $\ltuple{x_1}{x_m} = \ltuple{y_1, \ldots, y_m}{y_{m+k}}$
|
|
|
|
then $x_1 = \ltuple{y_1}{y_{k+1}}$.
|
|
|
|
\end{induction}
|
2023-08-13 16:03:41 +00:00
|
|
|
\noindent
|
|
|
|
We proceed by induction on $m$.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\paragraph{Base Case}%
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Suppose $\tuple{x_1} = \ltuple{y_1}{y_{1 + k}}$.
|
|
|
|
By definition of an \nameref{ref:n-tuple}, $\tuple{x_1} = x_1$.
|
|
|
|
Thus $x_1 = \ltuple{y_1}{y_{k + 1}}$.
|
|
|
|
Hence $P(1)$ holds true.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\paragraph{Inductive Step}%
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Suppose for $m \geq 1$ that $P(m)$ is true and assume
|
|
|
|
\begin{equation}
|
2023-08-13 18:39:50 +00:00
|
|
|
\hyperlabel{sec:lemma-0a-eq1}
|
2023-08-13 16:03:41 +00:00
|
|
|
\ltuple{x_1}{x_{m+1}} = \ltuple{y_1, \ldots, y_{m+1}}{y_{m+1+k}}.
|
|
|
|
\end{equation}
|
|
|
|
By definition of an \nameref{ref:n-tuple}, we can decompose
|
2023-08-13 18:39:50 +00:00
|
|
|
\eqref{sec:lemma-0a-eq1} into the following two identities
|
2023-08-13 16:03:41 +00:00
|
|
|
\begin{align*}
|
|
|
|
x_{m+1} & = y_{m+1+k} \\
|
|
|
|
\ltuple{x_1}{x_m} & = \ltuple{y_1}{y_{m+k}}.
|
|
|
|
\end{align*}
|
2023-08-13 18:39:50 +00:00
|
|
|
By \ihref{sec:lemma-0a-ih}, $P(m)$ implies $x_1 = \ltuple{y_1}{y_{k+1}}$.
|
2023-08-13 16:03:41 +00:00
|
|
|
Hence $P(m+1)$ holds true.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\paragraph{Conclusion}%
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
By induction, $P(m)$ holds true for all $m \geq 1$.
|
|
|
|
|
2023-08-09 13:39:41 +00:00
|
|
|
\end{proof}
|
2023-08-08 20:50:48 +00:00
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\chapter{Sentential Logic}%
|
|
|
|
\hyperlabel{chap:sentential-logic}
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\section{The Language of Sentential Logic}%
|
|
|
|
\hyperlabel{sec:language-sentential-logic}
|
|
|
|
|
2023-08-13 18:39:50 +00:00
|
|
|
\subsection{\unverified{Induction Principle}}%
|
2023-08-08 20:50:48 +00:00
|
|
|
\hyperlabel{sub:induction-principle-1}
|
|
|
|
|
2023-08-09 13:39:41 +00:00
|
|
|
\begin{theorem}
|
|
|
|
If $S$ is a set of wffs containing all the sentence symbols and closed under
|
|
|
|
all five formula-building operations, then $S$ is the set of \textit{all}
|
|
|
|
wffs.
|
|
|
|
\end{theorem}
|
2023-08-08 20:50:48 +00:00
|
|
|
|
2023-08-15 21:04:55 +00:00
|
|
|
\code{Bookshelf/Enderton/Logic/Chapter\_1}
|
|
|
|
{Enderton.Logic.Chapter\_1.Wff.rec}
|
|
|
|
|
2023-08-09 13:39:41 +00:00
|
|
|
\begin{proof}
|
2023-08-13 18:39:50 +00:00
|
|
|
We note every \nameref{ref:well-formed-formula} can be characterized by a
|
|
|
|
\nameref{ref:construction-sequence}.
|
|
|
|
For natural number $m$, let $P(m)$ be the statement:
|
|
|
|
\begin{induction}
|
|
|
|
\hyperlabel{sub:induction-principle-1-ih}
|
|
|
|
Every wff characterized by a construction sequence of length $m$ is in
|
|
|
|
$S$.
|
|
|
|
\end{induction}
|
|
|
|
\noindent
|
|
|
|
We proceed by strong induction on $m$.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\paragraph{Base Case}%
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Let $\phi$ denote a wff characterized by a construction sequence of length
|
|
|
|
$1$.
|
|
|
|
Then it must be that $\phi$ is a single sentence symbol.
|
|
|
|
By hypothesis, $S$ contains all the sentence symbols.
|
|
|
|
Thus $P(1)$ holds true.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\paragraph{Inductive Step}%
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Suppose $P(0)$, $P(1)$, $\ldots$, $P(m)$ holds true and let $\phi$ denote
|
|
|
|
a wff characterized by a construction sequence of length $m + 1$.
|
|
|
|
By definition of a construction sequence, one of the following holds:
|
|
|
|
\begin{align}
|
|
|
|
& \phi \text{ is a sentence symbol}
|
|
|
|
& \label{sub:induction-principle-1-eq1} \\
|
|
|
|
& \phi = \mathcal{E}_\neg(\epsilon_j)
|
|
|
|
\text{ for some } j < m + 1
|
|
|
|
& \label{sub:induction-principle-1-eq2} \\
|
|
|
|
& \phi = \mathcal{E}_\square(\epsilon_j, \epsilon_k)
|
|
|
|
\text{ for some } j < m + 1, k < m + 1
|
|
|
|
& \label{sub:induction-principle-1-eq3}
|
|
|
|
\end{align}
|
|
|
|
where $\square$ is one of the binary connectives $\land$, $\lor$,
|
|
|
|
$\Rightarrow$, $\Leftrightarrow$.
|
|
|
|
We consider each case in turn.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\subparagraph{\eqref{sub:induction-principle-1-eq1}}%
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
By hypothesis, all sentence symbols are in $S$.
|
|
|
|
Thus $\phi \in S$.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\subparagraph{\eqref{sub:induction-principle-1-eq2}}%
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Suppose $\phi = \mathcal{E}_\neg(\epsilon_j)$ for some $j < m + 1$.
|
|
|
|
By \ihref{sub:induction-principle-1-ih}, $\epsilon_j$ is in $S$.
|
|
|
|
By hypothesis, $S$ is closed under $\mathcal{E}_\neg$.
|
|
|
|
Thus $\phi \in S$.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\subparagraph{\eqref{sub:induction-principle-1-eq3}}%
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Suppose $\phi = \mathcal{E}_\square(\epsilon_j, \epsilon_k)$ for some
|
|
|
|
$j < m + 1, k < m + 1$,
|
|
|
|
By \ihref{sub:induction-principle-1-ih}, $\epsilon_j$ and $\epsilon_k$
|
|
|
|
is in $S$.
|
|
|
|
By hypothesis, $S$ is closed under $\mathcal{E}_\square$ for all
|
|
|
|
possible candidates of $\square$.
|
|
|
|
Thus $\phi \in S$.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\subparagraph{Subconclusion}%
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Since the above three cases are exhaustive, $P(m + 1)$ holds.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\paragraph{Conclusion}%
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
By strong induction, $P(m)$ holds true for all natural numbers $m \geq 1$.
|
|
|
|
Since every well-formed formula is characterized by a construction
|
|
|
|
sequence, the set of all wffs is a subset of $S$.
|
|
|
|
Likewise, it obviously holds that $S$ is a subset of all wffs.
|
|
|
|
Thus $S$ is precisely the set of all wffs.
|
|
|
|
|
2023-08-09 13:39:41 +00:00
|
|
|
\end{proof}
|
2023-08-08 20:50:48 +00:00
|
|
|
|
2023-08-15 21:04:55 +00:00
|
|
|
\subsection{\unverified{Balanced Parentheses}}%
|
|
|
|
\hyperlabel{sub:balanced-parentheses}
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\begin{lemma}
|
|
|
|
All well-formed formulas have an equal number of left and right parentheses.
|
|
|
|
\end{lemma}
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\begin{proof}
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Define $$S = \{ \phi \mid
|
|
|
|
\phi \text{ is a wff with a balanced number of parentheses} \}.$$
|
|
|
|
We prove that (i) all the sentence symbols are members of $S$ and (ii)
|
|
|
|
$S$ is closed under the five \nameref{ref:formula-building-operations}.
|
|
|
|
We then conclude with (iii) the proof of the theorem statement.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\paragraph{(i)}%
|
|
|
|
\hyperlabel{par:balanced-parentheses-i}
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
By definition, well-formed formulas comprising a single sentence symbol
|
|
|
|
do not have any parentheses.
|
|
|
|
Thus all sentence symbols are members of $S$.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\paragraph{(ii)}%
|
|
|
|
\hyperlabel{par:balanced-parentheses-ii}
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Let $\alpha, \beta \in S$.
|
|
|
|
By definition, $\mathcal{E}_{\neg}(\alpha) = (\neg\alpha)$.
|
|
|
|
Thus one additional left and right parenthesis is introduced.
|
|
|
|
Since $\alpha$ is assumed to have an equal number of left and right
|
|
|
|
parentheses, $\mathcal{E}_{\neg}(\alpha) \in S$.
|
|
|
|
Likewise,
|
|
|
|
$\mathcal{E}_{\square}(\alpha, \beta) = (\alpha \mathop{\square} \beta)$
|
|
|
|
where $\square$ is one of the binary connectives $\land$, $\lor$,
|
|
|
|
$\Rightarrow$, $\Leftrightarrow$.
|
|
|
|
Again, an additional left and right parenthesis is introduced.
|
|
|
|
Since $\alpha$ and $\beta$ are assumed to have a balanced number of
|
|
|
|
parentheses, $\mathcal{E}_{\square}(\alpha, \beta) \in S$.
|
|
|
|
Hence $S$ is closed under the five formula-building operations.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\paragraph{(iii)}%
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
By \nameref{par:balanced-parentheses-i} and
|
|
|
|
\nameref{par:balanced-parentheses-ii}, the
|
|
|
|
\nameref{sub:induction-principle-1} implies $S$ is the set of all wffs.
|
|
|
|
Thus all well-formed formulas have an equal number of left and right
|
|
|
|
parentheses.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\end{proof}
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\subsection{\verified{Parentheses Count}}%
|
|
|
|
\hyperlabel{sub:parentheses-count}
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\begin{lemma}
|
|
|
|
Let $\phi$ be a well-formed formula and $c$ be the number of places at which
|
|
|
|
a sentential connective symbol exists.
|
|
|
|
Then there is $2c$ parentheses in $\phi$.
|
|
|
|
\end{lemma}
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\code{Enderton.Logic.Chapter\_1}
|
|
|
|
{Enderton.Logic.Chapter\_1.paren\_count\_double\_sentential\_count}
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\begin{proof}
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Define $$S = \{ \phi \mid
|
|
|
|
\phi \text{ is a wff with } 2c \text{ parentheses} \}.$$
|
|
|
|
We prove that (i) all the sentence symbols are members of $S$ and (ii)
|
|
|
|
$S$ is closed under the five \nameref{ref:formula-building-operations}.
|
|
|
|
We then conclude with (iii) the proof of the theorem statement.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\paragraph{(i)}%
|
|
|
|
\hyperlabel{par:parentheses-count-i}
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
A sentence symbol, by itself, has no sentential connectives.
|
|
|
|
Likewise, it has 0 parentheses.
|
|
|
|
Thus $S$ contains every sentence symbol.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\paragraph{(ii)}%
|
|
|
|
\hyperlabel{par:parentheses-count-ii}
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Let $\alpha, \beta \in S$.
|
|
|
|
By definition, $\mathcal{E}_{\neg}(\alpha) = (\neg \alpha)$.
|
|
|
|
Then $\mathcal{E}_{\neg}(\alpha)$ introduces two additional parentheses
|
|
|
|
and one additional sentential connective symbol.
|
|
|
|
Thus $\mathcal{E}_{\neg}(\alpha) \in S$.
|
|
|
|
Likewise,
|
|
|
|
$\mathcal{E}_{\square}(\alpha, \beta) = (\alpha \mathop{\square} \beta)$
|
|
|
|
where $\square$ is one of the binary connectives $\land$, $\lor$,
|
|
|
|
$\Rightarrow$, $\Leftrightarrow$.
|
|
|
|
$\mathcal{E}_{\square}(\alpha, \beta)$ also introduces two additional
|
|
|
|
parentheses and one additional connective symbol.
|
|
|
|
Thus $\mathcal{E}_{\square}(\alpha, \beta) \in S$.
|
|
|
|
Hence $S$ is closed under the five formula-building operations.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\paragraph{(iii)}%
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
By \nameref{par:parentheses-count-i} and
|
|
|
|
\nameref{par:parentheses-count-ii}, the
|
|
|
|
\nameref{sub:induction-principle-1} implies $S$ is the set of all wffs.
|
|
|
|
Thus every wff has $2c$ parentheses in $\phi$, where $c$ denotes the
|
|
|
|
number of places at which a sentential connective symbol exists.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\end{proof}
|
|
|
|
|
2023-08-08 20:50:48 +00:00
|
|
|
\section{Exercises 1}%
|
|
|
|
\hyperlabel{sec:exercises-1}
|
|
|
|
|
2023-08-14 19:45:14 +00:00
|
|
|
\subsection{\unverified{Exercise 1.1.1}}%
|
2023-08-08 20:52:52 +00:00
|
|
|
\hyperlabel{sub:exercise-1.1.1}
|
2023-08-08 20:50:48 +00:00
|
|
|
|
2023-08-09 13:39:41 +00:00
|
|
|
Give three sentences in English together with translations into our formal
|
|
|
|
language.
|
2023-08-14 19:45:14 +00:00
|
|
|
The sentences should be chosen so as to have an interesting structure, and the
|
2023-08-09 13:39:41 +00:00
|
|
|
translations should each contain 15 or more symbols.
|
2023-08-08 20:50:48 +00:00
|
|
|
|
2023-08-09 13:39:41 +00:00
|
|
|
\begin{answer}
|
2023-08-14 19:45:14 +00:00
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
We begin first with the English sentences:
|
2023-08-15 21:04:55 +00:00
|
|
|
\begin{enumerate}[(i)]
|
2023-08-14 19:45:14 +00:00
|
|
|
\item He can juggle beach balls, bowling pins, and hackysacks unless
|
|
|
|
he is tired, in which case he can only juggle beach balls.
|
|
|
|
\item
|
|
|
|
If Lauren goes to the moves with Sam, he will watch Barbie and
|
|
|
|
eat popcorn, but if Lauren does not, he will watch Oppenheimer and
|
|
|
|
eat gummy worms.
|
|
|
|
\item
|
|
|
|
Trees produce oxygen if they are alive and well, able to pull
|
|
|
|
nutrients from the earth, and receive ample water.
|
|
|
|
\end{enumerate}
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\paragraph{(i)}%
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
We use the following translation: "To juggle beach balls" (B),
|
|
|
|
"to juggle bowling pins" (P), "to juggle hackysacks" (H), and
|
|
|
|
"he is tired" (T).
|
|
|
|
This yields the following translation:
|
|
|
|
$$(B \land ((\neg T) \Rightarrow (P \land H))).$$
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\paragraph{(ii)}%
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
We use the following translation: "Lauren goes to the movies" (L),
|
|
|
|
"Sam will watch Oppenheimer" (O), "Sam will watch "Barbie" (B),
|
|
|
|
"Sam will eat popcorn" (P), and "Sam will eay gummy worms" (G).
|
|
|
|
This yields the following translation:
|
|
|
|
$$(((L \land B) \land P) \lor (((\neg L) \land O) \land G)).$$
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\paragraph{(iii)}%
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
We use the following translation: "Trees produce oxygen" (O),
|
|
|
|
"the tree is alive" (A), "the tree is well" (W), "can pull nutrients
|
|
|
|
from the earth" (N), and "receives ample water" (R).
|
|
|
|
This yields the following translation:
|
|
|
|
$$(O \iff (((A \land W) \land N) \land R)).$$
|
|
|
|
|
2023-08-09 13:39:41 +00:00
|
|
|
\end{answer}
|
2023-08-08 20:50:48 +00:00
|
|
|
|
2023-08-15 02:37:09 +00:00
|
|
|
\subsection{\pending{Exercise 1.1.2}}%
|
2023-08-08 20:52:52 +00:00
|
|
|
\hyperlabel{sub:exercise-1.1.2}
|
2023-08-08 20:50:48 +00:00
|
|
|
|
2023-08-09 13:39:41 +00:00
|
|
|
Show that there are no wffs of length 2, 3, or 6, but that any other positive
|
|
|
|
length is possible.
|
2023-08-08 20:50:48 +00:00
|
|
|
|
2023-08-15 02:37:09 +00:00
|
|
|
\code*{Enderton.Logic.Chapter\_1}
|
|
|
|
{Enderton.Logic.Chapter\_1.exercise\_1\_1\_2\_i}
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\code{Enderton.Logic.Chapter\_1}
|
|
|
|
{Enderton.Logic.Chapter\_1.exercise\_1\_1\_2\_ii}
|
|
|
|
|
2023-08-09 13:39:41 +00:00
|
|
|
\begin{proof}
|
2023-08-14 19:45:14 +00:00
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Define $$S = \{ \phi \mid
|
|
|
|
\phi \text{ is a wff and the length of } \phi
|
|
|
|
\text{ is not } 2, 3, \text{or } 6. \}.$$
|
|
|
|
We prove that (i) all the sentence symbols are members of $S$ and (ii)
|
|
|
|
$S$ is closed under the five \nameref{ref:formula-building-operations}.
|
|
|
|
We then conclude with (iii) the proof of the theorem statement.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\paragraph{(i)}%
|
|
|
|
\hyperlabel{par:exercise-1.1.2-i}
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Sentence symbols, by definition, have length 1.
|
|
|
|
Thus every sentence symbol is a member of $S$.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\paragraph{(ii)}%
|
|
|
|
\hyperlabel{par:exercise-1.1.2-ii}
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Define $L$ to be the length function mapping arbitrary wff to its length.
|
2023-08-15 21:04:55 +00:00
|
|
|
Let $\alpha, \beta \in S$.
|
|
|
|
Then $L(\alpha)$ and $L(\beta)$ each evaluate to 1, 4, 5, or a value
|
|
|
|
larger than 6.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
By definition, $\mathcal{E}_{\neg}(\alpha) = (\neg \alpha)$.
|
|
|
|
Thus $L(\mathcal{E}_{\neg}(\alpha)) = L(\alpha) + 3$.
|
|
|
|
Enumerating through the possible values of $L(\alpha)$ shows
|
|
|
|
$\mathcal{E}_{\neg}(\alpha) \in S$.
|
2023-08-14 19:45:14 +00:00
|
|
|
Likewise,
|
2023-08-15 21:04:55 +00:00
|
|
|
$\mathcal{E}_{\square}(\alpha, \beta) = (\alpha \mathop{\square} \beta)$
|
2023-08-14 19:45:14 +00:00
|
|
|
where $\square$ is one of the binary connectives $\land$, $\lor$,
|
|
|
|
$\Rightarrow$, $\Leftrightarrow$.
|
2023-08-15 21:04:55 +00:00
|
|
|
Thus $L(\mathcal{E}_{\square}(\alpha, \beta)) = L(\alpha) + L(\beta) + 3$.
|
|
|
|
Again, enumerating through the possible values of $L(\alpha)$ and
|
|
|
|
$L(\beta)$ shows $\mathcal{E}_{\square}(\alpha, \beta) \in S$.
|
2023-08-14 19:45:14 +00:00
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Hence $S$ is closed under the five formula-building operations.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\paragraph{(iii)}%
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
By \nameref{par:exercise-1.1.2-i} and \nameref{par:exercise-1.1.2-ii}, the
|
|
|
|
\nameref{sub:induction-principle-1} implies $S$ is the set of all wffs.
|
|
|
|
It remains to be shown that a wff of any positive length excluding 2, 3,
|
|
|
|
and 6 are possible.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Let $\phi_1 = A_1$, $\phi_2 = (A_1 \land A_2)$, and
|
|
|
|
$\phi_3 = ((A_1 \land A_2) \land A_3)$.
|
|
|
|
Note these are wffs of lengths 1, 5, and 9 respectively.
|
|
|
|
Then $n$ repeated applications of $\mathcal{E}_{\neg}$ yields wffs of
|
|
|
|
length $1 + 3n$, $5 + 3n$, and $9 + 3n$ respectively.
|
|
|
|
But
|
|
|
|
\begin{align*}
|
|
|
|
& \{ 1 + 3n \mid n \in \mathbb{N} \}, \\
|
|
|
|
& \{ 5 + 3n \mid n \in \mathbb{N} \}, \text{ and } \\
|
|
|
|
& \{ 9 + 3n \mid n \in \mathbb{N} \}
|
|
|
|
\end{align*}
|
|
|
|
form a \nameref{S:ref:partition} of set $\mathbb{N} - \{ 2, 3, 6 \}$.
|
|
|
|
Thus a wff of any other positive length besides 2, 3, and 6 is possible.
|
|
|
|
|
2023-08-09 13:39:41 +00:00
|
|
|
\end{proof}
|
2023-08-08 20:50:48 +00:00
|
|
|
|
2023-08-15 21:04:55 +00:00
|
|
|
\subsection{\verified{Exercise 1.1.3}}%
|
2023-08-08 20:52:52 +00:00
|
|
|
\hyperlabel{sub:exercise-1.1.3}
|
2023-08-08 20:50:48 +00:00
|
|
|
|
2023-08-09 13:39:41 +00:00
|
|
|
Let $\alpha$ be a wff; let $c$ be the number of places at which binary
|
|
|
|
connective symbols $(\land, \lor, \Rightarrow, \Leftrightarrow)$ occur in
|
|
|
|
$\alpha$; let $s$ be the number of places at which sentence symbols occur in
|
|
|
|
$\alpha$.
|
|
|
|
(For example, if $\alpha$ is $(A \Rightarrow (\neg A))$ then $c = 1$ and
|
|
|
|
$s = 2$.)
|
|
|
|
Show by using the induction principle that $s = c + 1$.
|
2023-08-08 20:50:48 +00:00
|
|
|
|
2023-08-15 21:04:55 +00:00
|
|
|
\code*{Enderton.Logic.Chapter\_1}
|
|
|
|
{Enderton.Logic.Chapter\_1.exercise\_1\_1\_3}
|
|
|
|
|
2023-08-09 13:39:41 +00:00
|
|
|
\begin{proof}
|
2023-08-15 02:37:09 +00:00
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Define
|
|
|
|
\begin{equation}
|
|
|
|
\hyperlabel{sub:exercise-1.1.3-eq1}
|
|
|
|
S = \{\phi \mid \phi \text{ is a wff such that } s = c + 1\}.
|
|
|
|
\end{equation}
|
|
|
|
We prove that (i) all the sentence symbols are members of $S$ and (ii)
|
|
|
|
$S$ is closed under the five \nameref{ref:formula-building-operations}.
|
|
|
|
We then conclude with (iii) the proof of the theorem statement.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\paragraph{(i)}%
|
|
|
|
\hyperlabel{par:exercise-1.1.3-i}
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Let $\phi = A_n$ be an arbitrary sentence symbol.
|
|
|
|
The number of places at which sentence symbols occur in $\phi$ is 1.
|
|
|
|
The number of places at which binary connective symbols occur in $\phi$ is
|
|
|
|
0.
|
|
|
|
Hence $\phi \in S$.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\paragraph{(ii)}%
|
|
|
|
\hyperlabel{par:exercise-1.1.3-ii}
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Let $\alpha, \beta \in S$.
|
|
|
|
Denote the number of places at which sentence symbols occur in each as
|
|
|
|
$s_\alpha$ and $s_\beta$ respectively.
|
|
|
|
Likewise, denote the number of places at which binary connective symbols
|
|
|
|
occur as $c_\alpha$ and $c_\beta$.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
By definition, $\mathcal{E}_{\neg}(\alpha) = (\neg\alpha)$.
|
|
|
|
The number of sentence and binary connective symbols in
|
|
|
|
$\mathcal{E}_{\neg}(\alpha)$ does not change.
|
|
|
|
Thus $\mathcal{E}_{\neg}(\alpha) \in S$.
|
|
|
|
Likewise,
|
2023-08-15 21:04:55 +00:00
|
|
|
$\mathcal{E}_{\square}(\alpha, \beta) = (\alpha \mathop{\square} \beta)$
|
2023-08-15 02:37:09 +00:00
|
|
|
where $\square$ is one of the binary connectives $\land$, $\lor$,
|
|
|
|
$\Rightarrow$, $\Leftrightarrow$.
|
2023-08-15 21:04:55 +00:00
|
|
|
Therefore $\mathcal{E}_{\square}(\alpha, \beta)$ has $s_\alpha + s_\beta$
|
2023-08-15 02:37:09 +00:00
|
|
|
sentence symbols and $c_\alpha + c_\beta + 1$ binary connective symbols.
|
|
|
|
But \eqref{sub:exercise-1.1.3-eq1} implies
|
|
|
|
\begin{align*}
|
|
|
|
s_\alpha + s_\beta
|
|
|
|
& = (c_\alpha + 1) + (c_\beta + 1) \\
|
|
|
|
& = (c_\alpha + c_\beta + 1) + 1,
|
|
|
|
\end{align*}
|
2023-08-15 21:04:55 +00:00
|
|
|
meaning $\mathcal{E}_{\square}(\alpha, \beta) \in S$.
|
2023-08-15 02:37:09 +00:00
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Hence $S$ is closed under the five formula-building operations.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\paragraph{(iii)}%
|
|
|
|
\hyperlabel{par:exercise-1.1.3-iii}
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
By \nameref{par:exercise-1.1.3-i} and \nameref{par:exercise-1.1.3-ii}, the
|
|
|
|
\nameref{sub:induction-principle-1} indicates $S$ is the set of all
|
|
|
|
wffs.
|
|
|
|
|
2023-08-09 13:39:41 +00:00
|
|
|
\end{proof}
|
2023-08-08 20:50:48 +00:00
|
|
|
|
2023-08-15 02:37:09 +00:00
|
|
|
\subsection{\unverified{Exercise 1.1.4}}%
|
2023-08-08 20:52:52 +00:00
|
|
|
\hyperlabel{sub:exercise-1.1.4}
|
2023-08-08 20:50:48 +00:00
|
|
|
|
2023-08-09 13:39:41 +00:00
|
|
|
Assume we have a construction sequence ending in $\phi$, where $\phi$ does not
|
|
|
|
contain the symbol $A_4$.
|
|
|
|
Suppose we delete all the expressions in the construction sequence that
|
|
|
|
contain $A_4$.
|
|
|
|
Show that the result is still a legal construction sequence.
|
2023-08-08 20:50:48 +00:00
|
|
|
|
2023-08-09 13:39:41 +00:00
|
|
|
\begin{proof}
|
2023-08-15 02:37:09 +00:00
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Let $S$ denote a \nameref{ref:construction-sequence}
|
|
|
|
$\ltuple{\epsilon_1}{\epsilon_n}$ such that $\epsilon_n = \phi$.
|
|
|
|
Let $S' = \ltuple{\epsilon_{i_1}}{\epsilon_{i_m}}$ denote the construction
|
|
|
|
sequence resulting from deleting all expressions in $S$ containing $A_4$.
|
|
|
|
Fix $1 \leq j \leq m$.
|
|
|
|
Then there exists some $1 \leq k \leq n$ such that
|
|
|
|
$\epsilon_{i_j} = \epsilon_k$.
|
|
|
|
By definition of a construction sequence, there are three cases to consider:
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\paragraph{Case 1}%
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Suppose $\epsilon_k$ is a sentence symbol.
|
|
|
|
Then $\epsilon_{i_j}$ is also sentence symbol.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\paragraph{Case 2}%
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Suppose $\epsilon_k = \mathcal{E}_{\neg}(\epsilon_a)$ for some $a < k$.
|
|
|
|
It must be that $A_4$ is not found in $\epsilon_a$, else an immediate
|
|
|
|
contradiction is raised.
|
|
|
|
Therefore $\epsilon_a$ is a member of $S'$ that precedes $\epsilon_{i_j}$.
|
|
|
|
Hence $\epsilon_{i_j} = \mathcal{E}_{\neg}(\epsilon_{i_a})$ for some
|
|
|
|
$a < j$.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\paragraph{Case 3}%
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Suppose $\epsilon_k = \mathcal{E}_{\square}(\epsilon_a, \epsilon_b)$ for
|
|
|
|
some $a, b < k$ where $\square$ is one of the binary connectives
|
|
|
|
$\land$, $\lor$, $\Rightarrow$, $\Leftrightarrow$.
|
|
|
|
It must be that $A_4$ is found in neither $\epsilon_a$ nor $\epsilon_b$,
|
|
|
|
else an immediate contradiction is raised.
|
|
|
|
Therefore $\epsilon_a$ and $\epsilon_b$ is a member of $S'$, both of which
|
|
|
|
precede $\epsilon_{i_j}$.
|
|
|
|
Hence
|
|
|
|
$\epsilon_{i_j} = \mathcal{E}_{\square}(\epsilon_{i_a}, \epsilon_{i_b})$
|
|
|
|
for some $a, b < j$.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\paragraph{Conclusion}%
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Since the above cases are exhaustive and apply to an arbitrary member of
|
|
|
|
$S'$, it must be that every member of $S'$ is valid.
|
|
|
|
Hence $S'$ is still a legal construction sequence.
|
|
|
|
|
2023-08-09 13:39:41 +00:00
|
|
|
\end{proof}
|
2023-08-08 20:50:48 +00:00
|
|
|
|
2023-08-16 12:27:17 +00:00
|
|
|
\subsection{\verified{Exercise 1.1.5}}%
|
2023-08-08 20:52:52 +00:00
|
|
|
\hyperlabel{sub:exercise-1.1.5}
|
2023-08-08 20:50:48 +00:00
|
|
|
|
2023-08-09 13:39:41 +00:00
|
|
|
Suppose that $\alpha$ is a wff not containing the negation symbol $\neg$.
|
2023-08-15 02:37:09 +00:00
|
|
|
|
2023-08-15 21:04:55 +00:00
|
|
|
\subsubsection{\verified{Exercise 1.1.5a}}%
|
|
|
|
\hyperlabel{ssub:exercise-1.1.5.a}
|
2023-08-15 02:37:09 +00:00
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Show that the length of $\alpha$ (i.e., the number of symbols in the string)
|
|
|
|
is odd.
|
2023-08-09 13:39:41 +00:00
|
|
|
\textit{Suggestion}: Apply induction to show that the length is of the form
|
2023-08-15 02:37:09 +00:00
|
|
|
$4k + 1$.
|
|
|
|
|
2023-08-15 21:04:55 +00:00
|
|
|
\code*{Enderton.Logic.Chapter\_1}
|
|
|
|
{Enderton.Logic.Chapter\_1.exercise\_1\_1\_5\_a}
|
|
|
|
|
2023-08-15 02:37:09 +00:00
|
|
|
\begin{proof}
|
2023-08-15 21:04:55 +00:00
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Define $L$ to be the length function mapping arbitrary
|
|
|
|
\nameref{ref:well-formed-formula} to its length and let
|
|
|
|
\begin{equation}
|
|
|
|
\hyperlabel{ssub:exercise-1.1.5.a-eq1}
|
|
|
|
S = \{\phi \mid
|
|
|
|
\phi \text{ is a wff containing } \neg \text{ or }
|
|
|
|
\exists k \in \mathbb{N}, L(\phi) = 4k + 1\}.
|
|
|
|
\end{equation}
|
|
|
|
We prove that (i) all the sentence symbols are members of $S$ and (ii)
|
|
|
|
$S$ is closed under the five \nameref{ref:formula-building-operations}.
|
|
|
|
We then conclude with (iii) the proof of the theorem statement.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\paragraph{(i)}%
|
|
|
|
\hyperlabel{par:exercise-1.1.5.a-i}
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Every sentence symbol has length 1 by definition.
|
|
|
|
That is, every sentence symbol has length $(4)(0) + 1$.
|
|
|
|
Hence $S$ contains every sentence symbol.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\paragraph{(ii)}%
|
|
|
|
\hyperlabel{par:exercise-1.1.5.a-ii}
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Let $\alpha, \beta \in S$.
|
|
|
|
Then there exists some $k_\alpha$ and $k_\beta$ such that
|
|
|
|
$L(\alpha) = 4k_\alpha + 1$ and $L(\beta) = 4k_\beta + 1$.
|
|
|
|
Clearly $S$ is closed under $\mathcal{E}_{\neg}$.
|
|
|
|
Next consider
|
|
|
|
$\mathcal{E}_{\square}(\alpha, \beta) = (\alpha \mathop{\square} \beta)$
|
|
|
|
where $\square$ is one of the binary connectives $\land$, $\lor$,
|
|
|
|
$\Rightarrow$, $\Leftrightarrow$.
|
|
|
|
Then
|
|
|
|
\begin{align*}
|
|
|
|
L(\alpha, \beta)
|
|
|
|
& = L(\alpha) + L(\beta) + 3 \\
|
|
|
|
& = (4k_\alpha + 1) + (4k_\beta + 1) + 3 \\
|
|
|
|
& = 4k_\alpha + 4k_\beta + 4 + 1 \\
|
|
|
|
& = 4(k_\alpha + k_\beta + 1) + 1.
|
|
|
|
\end{align*}
|
|
|
|
Therefore, there exists a $k \in \mathbb{N}$, namely
|
|
|
|
$k = k_\alpha + k_\beta + 1$, such that
|
|
|
|
$L(\mathcal{E}_{\square}(\alpha, \beta)) = 4k + 1$.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Hence $S$ is closed under the five formula-building operations.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
\paragraph{(iii)}%
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
By \nameref{par:exercise-1.1.5.a-i} and \nameref{par:exercise-1.1.5.a-ii},
|
|
|
|
the \nameref{sub:induction-principle-1} indicates $S$ is the set of all
|
|
|
|
wffs.
|
|
|
|
Thus all well-formed formulas not containing symbol $\neg$ has length
|
|
|
|
$4k + 1$ for some $k \in \mathbb{N}$.
|
|
|
|
Therefore these well-formed formulas have odd length.
|
|
|
|
|
2023-08-15 02:37:09 +00:00
|
|
|
\end{proof}
|
|
|
|
|
2023-08-16 12:27:17 +00:00
|
|
|
\subsubsection{\verified{Exercise 1.1.5b}}%
|
2023-08-15 21:04:55 +00:00
|
|
|
\hyperlabel{ssub:exercise-1.1.5-b}
|
2023-08-15 02:37:09 +00:00
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Show that more than a quarter of the symbols are sentence symbols.
|
|
|
|
\textit{Suggestion}: Apply induction to show that the number of sentence
|
2023-08-15 21:04:55 +00:00
|
|
|
symbols is of the form $k + 1$.
|
2023-08-08 20:50:48 +00:00
|
|
|
|
2023-08-15 21:04:55 +00:00
|
|
|
\code*{Enderton.Logic.Chapter\_1}
|
|
|
|
{Enderton.Logic.Chapter\_1.exercise\_1\_1\_5\_b}
|
2023-08-08 20:50:48 +00:00
|
|
|
|
2023-08-15 21:04:55 +00:00
|
|
|
\begin{proof}
|
2023-08-08 20:50:48 +00:00
|
|
|
|
2023-08-15 21:04:55 +00:00
|
|
|
Let $\phi$ be a \nameref{ref:well-formed-formula}.
|
|
|
|
By \nameref{sub:exercise-1.1.3}, the number of sentence symbols of $\phi$ is
|
|
|
|
$k + 1$, where $k$ is the number of places at which binary connective
|
|
|
|
symbols occur in $\phi$.
|
|
|
|
By \nameref{sub:parentheses-count}, the number of parentheses in $\phi$ is
|
|
|
|
$2k$.
|
|
|
|
Thus $\phi$ has length $(k + 1) + k + 2k = 4k + 1$.
|
|
|
|
But $$\frac{k + 1}{4k + 1} > \frac{k + 1}{4k + 4} = \frac{1}{4}.$$
|
|
|
|
Hence more than a quarter of the symbols of $\phi$ are sentence symbols.
|
2023-08-08 20:50:48 +00:00
|
|
|
|
2023-08-09 13:39:41 +00:00
|
|
|
\end{proof}
|
2023-08-08 20:50:48 +00:00
|
|
|
|
2023-05-13 12:59:28 +00:00
|
|
|
\end{document}
|