Enderton. Finish ordering on natural numbers exercises.
parent
11d25dd28c
commit
5dfb2f12cf
|
@ -6950,7 +6950,7 @@ Show that $<_L$ is a linear ordering on $A \times B$.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
\begin{proof}
|
\begin{proof}
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
\lean{Init/Prelude}{Nat.succ}
|
\lean{Std/Data/Nat/Lemmas}{Nat.succ\_eq\_one\_add}
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
Let
|
Let
|
||||||
\begin{equation}
|
\begin{equation}
|
||||||
|
@ -7605,7 +7605,7 @@ Formulate an analogue to Exercise 9 for a function
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
\end{proof}
|
\end{proof}
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
\subsection{\sorry{Exercise 4.13}}%
|
\subsection{\verified{Exercise 4.13}}%
|
||||||
\hyperlabel{sub:exercise-4.13}
|
\hyperlabel{sub:exercise-4.13}
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
Let $m$ and $n$ be natural numbers such that $m \cdot n = 0$.
|
Let $m$ and $n$ be natural numbers such that $m \cdot n = 0$.
|
||||||
|
@ -7613,11 +7613,29 @@ Show that either $m = 0$ or $n = 0$.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
\begin{proof}
|
\begin{proof}
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
TODO
|
\lean{Bookshelf/Enderton/Set/Chapter\_4}
|
||||||
|
{Enderton.Set.Chapter\_4.exercise\_4\_13}
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
Suppose $m \cdot n = 0$.
|
||||||
|
For the sake of contradiction, assume $m \neq 0$ and $n \neq 0$.
|
||||||
|
By \nameref{sub:theorem-4c}, there exists some $p, q \in \omega$ such that
|
||||||
|
$p^+ = m$ and $q^+ = n$.
|
||||||
|
Thus
|
||||||
|
\begin{align*}
|
||||||
|
m \cdot n
|
||||||
|
& = m \cdot q^+ \\
|
||||||
|
& = m \cdot q + m & \textref{sub:theorem-4j} \\
|
||||||
|
& = m \cdot q + p^+ \\
|
||||||
|
& = (m \cdot q + p)^+. & \textref{sub:theorem-4i}
|
||||||
|
\end{align*}
|
||||||
|
By definition of a \nameref{ref:successor},
|
||||||
|
$m \cdot n = (m \cdot q + p)^+ \neq \emptyset = 0$, a contradiction.
|
||||||
|
Therefore our original assumption was wrong.
|
||||||
|
Hence $m = 0$ or $n = 0$.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
\end{proof}
|
\end{proof}
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
\subsection{\sorry{Exercise 4.14}}%
|
\subsection{\verified{Exercise 4.14}}%
|
||||||
\hyperlabel{sub:exercise-4.14}
|
\hyperlabel{sub:exercise-4.14}
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
Call a natural number \textit{even} if it has the form $2 \cdot m$ for some $m$.
|
Call a natural number \textit{even} if it has the form $2 \cdot m$ for some $m$.
|
||||||
|
@ -7626,7 +7644,98 @@ Show that each natural number is either even or odd, but never both.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
\begin{proof}
|
\begin{proof}
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
TODO
|
\lean{Bookshelf/Enderton/Set/Chapter\_4}
|
||||||
|
{Enderton.Set.Chapter\_4.exercise\_4\_14}
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
Let $$S = \{n \in \omega \mid n \text{ is even or odd but not both}\}.$$
|
||||||
|
We show that (i) $0 \in S$ and (ii) if $n \in S$ then $n^+ \in S$ as well.
|
||||||
|
Afterward we prove (iii) that the theorem statement holds.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
\paragraph{(i)}%
|
||||||
|
\hyperlabel{par:exercise-4.14a-i}
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
$0$ is even since $2 \cdot 0 = 0$ by \nameref{sub:theorem-4j}.
|
||||||
|
Furthermore, $0$ is not odd since that would imply there exists some
|
||||||
|
$p$ such that $(2 \cdot p)^+ = 0$.
|
||||||
|
By definition of \nameref{ref:successor}, this is not possible.
|
||||||
|
Thus $0 \in S$.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
\paragraph{(ii)}%
|
||||||
|
\hyperlabel{par:exercise-4.14a-ii}
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
Suppose $n \in S$.
|
||||||
|
Then $n$ is even or odd but not both.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
\subparagraph{Case 1}%
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
Suppose $n$ is even and not odd.
|
||||||
|
Then there exists some $m \in \omega$ such that $2 \cdot m = n$.
|
||||||
|
Since the successor operation is one-to-one, $(2 \cdot m)^+ = n^+$.
|
||||||
|
Thus $n^+$ is odd.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
For the sake of contradiction, suppose $n^+$ is even.
|
||||||
|
Then there exists some $p$ such that $2 \cdot p = n^+$.
|
||||||
|
We consider two additional cases:
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
\vspace{8pt}\quad
|
||||||
|
\textbf{Case 1a}: Suppose $p = 0$.
|
||||||
|
Then, by \nameref{sub:theorem-4j}, $2 \cdot p = 0 = n^+$.
|
||||||
|
By definition of \nameref{ref:successor}, this is not possible.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
\vspace{8pt}\quad
|
||||||
|
\textbf{Case 1b}: Suppose $p \neq 0$.
|
||||||
|
Then \nameref{sub:theorem-4c} implies there exists some $q$ such that
|
||||||
|
$q^+ = p$.
|
||||||
|
Thus
|
||||||
|
\begin{align*}
|
||||||
|
n^+
|
||||||
|
& = 2 \cdot p \\
|
||||||
|
& = 2 \cdot q^+ \\
|
||||||
|
& = q^+ + q^+ \\
|
||||||
|
& = (q^+ + q)^+. & \textref{sub:theorem-4i}
|
||||||
|
\end{align*}
|
||||||
|
Since the successor operation is one-to-one, $n = q^+ + q$.
|
||||||
|
But then
|
||||||
|
\begin{align*}
|
||||||
|
n
|
||||||
|
& = q^+ + q \\
|
||||||
|
& = q + q^+ & \textref{sub:theorem-4k-2} \\
|
||||||
|
& = (q + q)^+ & \textref{sub:theorem-4i} \\
|
||||||
|
& = (2 \cdot q)^+,
|
||||||
|
\end{align*}
|
||||||
|
indicating $n$ is odd.
|
||||||
|
This is a contradiction.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
\vspace{8pt}\quad
|
||||||
|
\textbf{Conclusion}: Since the above two cases are exhaustive, it follows
|
||||||
|
our original assumption is wrong.
|
||||||
|
That is, $n^+$ is odd but not even.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
\subparagraph{Case 2}%
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
Suppose $n$ is odd and not even.
|
||||||
|
Then there exists some $p \in \omega$ such that $(2 \cdot p)^+ = n$.
|
||||||
|
Since the successor operation is one-to-one,
|
||||||
|
$(2 \cdot p)^{++} = (2 \cdot p^+) = n^+$.
|
||||||
|
Thus $n^+$ is even.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
For the sake of contradiction, suppose $n^+$ is odd.
|
||||||
|
Then there exists some $q$ such that $(2 \cdot q)^+ = n^+$.
|
||||||
|
Since the successor operation is one-to-one, it follows $2 \cdot q = n$.
|
||||||
|
But this implies $n$ is even, a contradiction.
|
||||||
|
Thus our original assumption is wrong.
|
||||||
|
That is, $n^+$ is even but not odd.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
\subparagraph{Conclusion}%
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
Since the foregoing cases are exhaustive, it follows $n^+ \in S$.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
\paragraph{(iii)}%
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
By \nameref{par:exercise-4.14a-i} and \nameref{par:exercise-4.14a-ii},
|
||||||
|
$S$ is an \nameref{ref:inductive-set}.
|
||||||
|
By \nameref{sub:theorem-4b}, $S = \omega$.
|
||||||
|
Thus every natural number is either even or odd, but not both.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
\end{proof}
|
\end{proof}
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
|
|
@ -1,3 +1,4 @@
|
||||||
|
import Common.Logic.Basic
|
||||||
import Mathlib.Data.Set.Basic
|
import Mathlib.Data.Set.Basic
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
/-! # Enderton.Set.Chapter_4
|
/-! # Enderton.Set.Chapter_4
|
||||||
|
@ -24,4 +25,84 @@ Show that `1 ≠ 3` i.e., that `∅⁺ ≠ ∅⁺⁺⁺`.
|
||||||
theorem exercise_4_1 : 1 ≠ 3 := by
|
theorem exercise_4_1 : 1 ≠ 3 := by
|
||||||
simp
|
simp
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
/-- #### Exercise 4.13
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
Let `m` and `n` be natural numbers such that `m ⬝ n = 0`. Show that either
|
||||||
|
`m = 0` or `n = 0`.
|
||||||
|
-/
|
||||||
|
theorem exercise_4_13 (m n : ℕ) (h : m * n = 0)
|
||||||
|
: m = 0 ∨ n = 0 := by
|
||||||
|
by_contra nh
|
||||||
|
rw [not_or_de_morgan] at nh
|
||||||
|
have ⟨p, hp⟩ : ∃ p, m = p.succ := Nat.exists_eq_succ_of_ne_zero nh.left
|
||||||
|
have ⟨q, hq⟩ : ∃ q, n = q.succ := Nat.exists_eq_succ_of_ne_zero nh.right
|
||||||
|
have : m * n = (m * q + p).succ := calc m * n
|
||||||
|
_ = m * q.succ := by rw [hq]
|
||||||
|
_ = m * q + m := rfl
|
||||||
|
_ = m * q + p.succ := by rw [hp]
|
||||||
|
_ = (m * q + p).succ := rfl
|
||||||
|
rw [this] at h
|
||||||
|
simp only [Nat.succ_ne_zero] at h
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
/--
|
||||||
|
Call a natural number *even* if it has the form `2 ⬝ m` for some `m`.
|
||||||
|
-/
|
||||||
|
def even (n : ℕ) : Prop := ∃ m, 2 * m = n
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
/--
|
||||||
|
Call a natural number *odd* if it has the form `(2 ⬝ p) + 1` for some `p`.
|
||||||
|
-/
|
||||||
|
def odd (n : ℕ) : Prop := ∃ p, (2 * p) + 1 = n
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
/-- #### Exercise 4.14
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
Show that each natural number is either even or odd, but never both.
|
||||||
|
-/
|
||||||
|
theorem exercise_4_14 (n : ℕ)
|
||||||
|
: (even n ∧ ¬ odd n) ∨ (¬ even n ∧ odd n) := by
|
||||||
|
induction n with
|
||||||
|
| zero =>
|
||||||
|
left
|
||||||
|
refine ⟨⟨0, by simp⟩, ?_⟩
|
||||||
|
intro ⟨p, hp⟩
|
||||||
|
simp only [Nat.zero_eq, Nat.succ_ne_zero] at hp
|
||||||
|
| succ n ih =>
|
||||||
|
apply Or.elim ih
|
||||||
|
· -- Assumes `n` is even meaning `n⁺` is odd.
|
||||||
|
intro ⟨⟨m, hm⟩, h⟩
|
||||||
|
right
|
||||||
|
refine ⟨?_, ⟨m, by rw [← hm]⟩⟩
|
||||||
|
by_contra nh
|
||||||
|
have ⟨p, hp⟩ := nh
|
||||||
|
by_cases hp' : p = 0
|
||||||
|
· rw [hp'] at hp
|
||||||
|
simp at hp
|
||||||
|
· have ⟨q, hq⟩ := Nat.exists_eq_succ_of_ne_zero hp'
|
||||||
|
rw [hq] at hp
|
||||||
|
have hq₁ : (q.succ + q).succ = n.succ := calc (q.succ + q).succ
|
||||||
|
_ = q.succ + q.succ := rfl
|
||||||
|
_ = 2 * q.succ := by rw [Nat.two_mul]
|
||||||
|
_ = n.succ := hp
|
||||||
|
injection hq₁ with hq₂
|
||||||
|
have : odd n := by
|
||||||
|
refine ⟨q, ?_⟩
|
||||||
|
calc 2 * q + 1
|
||||||
|
_ = q + q + 1 := by rw [Nat.two_mul]
|
||||||
|
_ = q + q.succ := rfl
|
||||||
|
_ = q.succ + q := by rw [Nat.add_comm]
|
||||||
|
_ = n := hq₂
|
||||||
|
exact absurd this h
|
||||||
|
· -- Assumes `n` is odd meaning `n⁺` is even.
|
||||||
|
intro ⟨h, ⟨p, hp⟩⟩
|
||||||
|
have hp' : 2 * p.succ = n.succ := congrArg Nat.succ hp
|
||||||
|
left
|
||||||
|
refine ⟨⟨p.succ, by rw [← hp']⟩, ?_⟩
|
||||||
|
by_contra nh
|
||||||
|
unfold odd at nh
|
||||||
|
have ⟨q, hq⟩ := nh
|
||||||
|
injection hq with hq'
|
||||||
|
simp only [Nat.add_eq, Nat.add_zero] at hq'
|
||||||
|
have : even n := ⟨q, hq'⟩
|
||||||
|
exact absurd this h
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
end Enderton.Set.Chapter_4
|
end Enderton.Set.Chapter_4
|
Loading…
Reference in New Issue