Enderton (logic). Continue working through section 1.1.

finite-set-exercises
Joshua Potter 2023-08-15 15:04:55 -06:00
parent 91cdf1540e
commit 456303f1dc
3 changed files with 404 additions and 74 deletions

View File

@ -63,7 +63,7 @@
\end{align*}
\code*{Bookshelf/Enderton/Logic/Chapter\_1}
{Enderton.Logic.Chapter\_1.WFF}
{Enderton.Logic.Chapter\_1.Wff}
\lean{Init/Prelude}
{Not}
@ -96,7 +96,7 @@
times the \nameref{ref:formula-building-operations}.
\code*{Bookshelf/Enderton/Logic/Chapter\_1}
{Enderton.Logic.Chapter\_1.WFF}
{Enderton.Logic.Chapter\_1.Wff}
\endgroup
@ -169,6 +169,9 @@
wffs.
\end{theorem}
\code{Bookshelf/Enderton/Logic/Chapter\_1}
{Enderton.Logic.Chapter\_1.Wff.rec}
\begin{proof}
We note every \nameref{ref:well-formed-formula} can be characterized by a
\nameref{ref:construction-sequence}.
@ -244,6 +247,109 @@
\end{proof}
\subsection{\unverified{Balanced Parentheses}}%
\hyperlabel{sub:balanced-parentheses}
\begin{lemma}
All well-formed formulas have an equal number of left and right parentheses.
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}
Define $$S = \{ \phi \mid
\phi \text{ is a wff with a balanced number of parentheses} \}.$$
We prove that (i) all the sentence symbols are members of $S$ and (ii)
$S$ is closed under the five \nameref{ref:formula-building-operations}.
We then conclude with (iii) the proof of the theorem statement.
\paragraph{(i)}%
\hyperlabel{par:balanced-parentheses-i}
By definition, well-formed formulas comprising a single sentence symbol
do not have any parentheses.
Thus all sentence symbols are members of $S$.
\paragraph{(ii)}%
\hyperlabel{par:balanced-parentheses-ii}
Let $\alpha, \beta \in S$.
By definition, $\mathcal{E}_{\neg}(\alpha) = (\neg\alpha)$.
Thus one additional left and right parenthesis is introduced.
Since $\alpha$ is assumed to have an equal number of left and right
parentheses, $\mathcal{E}_{\neg}(\alpha) \in S$.
Likewise,
$\mathcal{E}_{\square}(\alpha, \beta) = (\alpha \mathop{\square} \beta)$
where $\square$ is one of the binary connectives $\land$, $\lor$,
$\Rightarrow$, $\Leftrightarrow$.
Again, an additional left and right parenthesis is introduced.
Since $\alpha$ and $\beta$ are assumed to have a balanced number of
parentheses, $\mathcal{E}_{\square}(\alpha, \beta) \in S$.
Hence $S$ is closed under the five formula-building operations.
\paragraph{(iii)}%
By \nameref{par:balanced-parentheses-i} and
\nameref{par:balanced-parentheses-ii}, the
\nameref{sub:induction-principle-1} implies $S$ is the set of all wffs.
Thus all well-formed formulas have an equal number of left and right
parentheses.
\end{proof}
\subsection{\verified{Parentheses Count}}%
\hyperlabel{sub:parentheses-count}
\begin{lemma}
Let $\phi$ be a well-formed formula and $c$ be the number of places at which
a sentential connective symbol exists.
Then there is $2c$ parentheses in $\phi$.
\end{lemma}
\code{Enderton.Logic.Chapter\_1}
{Enderton.Logic.Chapter\_1.paren\_count\_double\_sentential\_count}
\begin{proof}
Define $$S = \{ \phi \mid
\phi \text{ is a wff with } 2c \text{ parentheses} \}.$$
We prove that (i) all the sentence symbols are members of $S$ and (ii)
$S$ is closed under the five \nameref{ref:formula-building-operations}.
We then conclude with (iii) the proof of the theorem statement.
\paragraph{(i)}%
\hyperlabel{par:parentheses-count-i}
A sentence symbol, by itself, has no sentential connectives.
Likewise, it has 0 parentheses.
Thus $S$ contains every sentence symbol.
\paragraph{(ii)}%
\hyperlabel{par:parentheses-count-ii}
Let $\alpha, \beta \in S$.
By definition, $\mathcal{E}_{\neg}(\alpha) = (\neg \alpha)$.
Then $\mathcal{E}_{\neg}(\alpha)$ introduces two additional parentheses
and one additional sentential connective symbol.
Thus $\mathcal{E}_{\neg}(\alpha) \in S$.
Likewise,
$\mathcal{E}_{\square}(\alpha, \beta) = (\alpha \mathop{\square} \beta)$
where $\square$ is one of the binary connectives $\land$, $\lor$,
$\Rightarrow$, $\Leftrightarrow$.
$\mathcal{E}_{\square}(\alpha, \beta)$ also introduces two additional
parentheses and one additional connective symbol.
Thus $\mathcal{E}_{\square}(\alpha, \beta) \in S$.
Hence $S$ is closed under the five formula-building operations.
\paragraph{(iii)}%
By \nameref{par:parentheses-count-i} and
\nameref{par:parentheses-count-ii}, the
\nameref{sub:induction-principle-1} implies $S$ is the set of all wffs.
Thus every wff has $2c$ parentheses in $\phi$, where $c$ denotes the
number of places at which a sentential connective symbol exists.
\end{proof}
\section{Exercises 1}%
\hyperlabel{sec:exercises-1}
@ -258,7 +364,7 @@
\begin{answer}
We begin first with the English sentences:
\begin{enumerate}[i]
\begin{enumerate}[(i)]
\item He can juggle beach balls, bowling pins, and hackysacks unless
he is tired, in which case he can only juggle beach balls.
\item
@ -327,21 +433,21 @@
\hyperlabel{par:exercise-1.1.2-ii}
Define $L$ to be the length function mapping arbitrary wff to its length.
Let $\phi, \psi \in S$.
Then $L(\phi)$ and $L(\psi)$ each evaluate to 1, 4, 5, or a value larger
than 6.
Let $\alpha, \beta \in S$.
Then $L(\alpha)$ and $L(\beta)$ each evaluate to 1, 4, 5, or a value
larger than 6.
By definition, $\mathcal{E}_{\neg}(\phi) = (\neg \phi)$.
Thus $L(\mathcal{E}_{\neg}(\phi)) = L(\phi) + 3$.
Enumerating through the possible values of $L(\phi)$ shows
$\mathcal{E}_{\neg}(\phi) \in S$.
By definition, $\mathcal{E}_{\neg}(\alpha) = (\neg \alpha)$.
Thus $L(\mathcal{E}_{\neg}(\alpha)) = L(\alpha) + 3$.
Enumerating through the possible values of $L(\alpha)$ shows
$\mathcal{E}_{\neg}(\alpha) \in S$.
Likewise,
$\mathcal{E}_{\square}(\phi, \psi) = (\phi \mathop{\square} \psi)$
$\mathcal{E}_{\square}(\alpha, \beta) = (\alpha \mathop{\square} \beta)$
where $\square$ is one of the binary connectives $\land$, $\lor$,
$\Rightarrow$, $\Leftrightarrow$.
Thus $L(\mathcal{E}_{\square}(\phi, \psi)) = L(\phi) + L(\psi) + 3$.
Again, enumerating through the possible values of $L(\phi)$ and $L(\psi)$
shows $\mathcal{E}_{\square}(\phi, \psi) \in S$.
Thus $L(\mathcal{E}_{\square}(\alpha, \beta)) = L(\alpha) + L(\beta) + 3$.
Again, enumerating through the possible values of $L(\alpha)$ and
$L(\beta)$ shows $\mathcal{E}_{\square}(\alpha, \beta) \in S$.
Hence $S$ is closed under the five formula-building operations.
@ -368,7 +474,7 @@
\end{proof}
\subsection{\pending{Exercise 1.1.3}}%
\subsection{\verified{Exercise 1.1.3}}%
\hyperlabel{sub:exercise-1.1.3}
Let $\alpha$ be a wff; let $c$ be the number of places at which binary
@ -379,6 +485,9 @@
$s = 2$.)
Show by using the induction principle that $s = c + 1$.
\code*{Enderton.Logic.Chapter\_1}
{Enderton.Logic.Chapter\_1.exercise\_1\_1\_3}
\begin{proof}
Define
@ -413,10 +522,10 @@
$\mathcal{E}_{\neg}(\alpha)$ does not change.
Thus $\mathcal{E}_{\neg}(\alpha) \in S$.
Likewise,
$\mathcal{E}_{\square}(\phi, \psi) = (\phi \mathop{\square} \psi)$
$\mathcal{E}_{\square}(\alpha, \beta) = (\alpha \mathop{\square} \beta)$
where $\square$ is one of the binary connectives $\land$, $\lor$,
$\Rightarrow$, $\Leftrightarrow$.
Therefore $\mathcal{E}_{\square}(\phi, \psi)$ has $s_\alpha + s_\beta$
Therefore $\mathcal{E}_{\square}(\alpha, \beta)$ has $s_\alpha + s_\beta$
sentence symbols and $c_\alpha + c_\beta + 1$ binary connective symbols.
But \eqref{sub:exercise-1.1.3-eq1} implies
\begin{align*}
@ -424,7 +533,7 @@
& = (c_\alpha + 1) + (c_\beta + 1) \\
& = (c_\alpha + c_\beta + 1) + 1,
\end{align*}
meaning $\mathcal{E}_{\square}(\phi, \psi) \in S$.
meaning $\mathcal{E}_{\square}(\alpha, \beta) \in S$.
Hence $S$ is closed under the five formula-building operations.
@ -493,46 +602,101 @@
\end{proof}
\subsection{\sorry{Exercise 1.1.5}}%
\subsection{\pending{Exercise 1.1.5}}%
\hyperlabel{sub:exercise-1.1.5}
Suppose that $\alpha$ is a wff not containing the negation symbol $\neg$.
\subsubsection{\sorry{Exercise 1.1.5a}}%
\hyperlabel{ssub:exercise-1.1.5-a}
\subsubsection{\verified{Exercise 1.1.5a}}%
\hyperlabel{ssub:exercise-1.1.5.a}
Show that the length of $\alpha$ (i.e., the number of symbols in the string)
is odd.
\textit{Suggestion}: Apply induction to show that the length is of the form
$4k + 1$.
\code*{Enderton.Logic.Chapter\_1}
{Enderton.Logic.Chapter\_1.exercise\_1\_1\_5\_a}
\begin{proof}
TODO
Define $L$ to be the length function mapping arbitrary
\nameref{ref:well-formed-formula} to its length and let
\begin{equation}
\hyperlabel{ssub:exercise-1.1.5.a-eq1}
S = \{\phi \mid
\phi \text{ is a wff containing } \neg \text{ or }
\exists k \in \mathbb{N}, L(\phi) = 4k + 1\}.
\end{equation}
We prove that (i) all the sentence symbols are members of $S$ and (ii)
$S$ is closed under the five \nameref{ref:formula-building-operations}.
We then conclude with (iii) the proof of the theorem statement.
\paragraph{(i)}%
\hyperlabel{par:exercise-1.1.5.a-i}
Every sentence symbol has length 1 by definition.
That is, every sentence symbol has length $(4)(0) + 1$.
Hence $S$ contains every sentence symbol.
\paragraph{(ii)}%
\hyperlabel{par:exercise-1.1.5.a-ii}
Let $\alpha, \beta \in S$.
Then there exists some $k_\alpha$ and $k_\beta$ such that
$L(\alpha) = 4k_\alpha + 1$ and $L(\beta) = 4k_\beta + 1$.
Clearly $S$ is closed under $\mathcal{E}_{\neg}$.
Next consider
$\mathcal{E}_{\square}(\alpha, \beta) = (\alpha \mathop{\square} \beta)$
where $\square$ is one of the binary connectives $\land$, $\lor$,
$\Rightarrow$, $\Leftrightarrow$.
Then
\begin{align*}
L(\alpha, \beta)
& = L(\alpha) + L(\beta) + 3 \\
& = (4k_\alpha + 1) + (4k_\beta + 1) + 3 \\
& = 4k_\alpha + 4k_\beta + 4 + 1 \\
& = 4(k_\alpha + k_\beta + 1) + 1.
\end{align*}
Therefore, there exists a $k \in \mathbb{N}$, namely
$k = k_\alpha + k_\beta + 1$, such that
$L(\mathcal{E}_{\square}(\alpha, \beta)) = 4k + 1$.
Hence $S$ is closed under the five formula-building operations.
\paragraph{(iii)}%
By \nameref{par:exercise-1.1.5.a-i} and \nameref{par:exercise-1.1.5.a-ii},
the \nameref{sub:induction-principle-1} indicates $S$ is the set of all
wffs.
Thus all well-formed formulas not containing symbol $\neg$ has length
$4k + 1$ for some $k \in \mathbb{N}$.
Therefore these well-formed formulas have odd length.
\end{proof}
\subsubsection{\sorry{Exercise 1.1.6a}}%
\hyperlabel{ssub:exercise-1.1.6-a}
\subsubsection{\pending{Exercise 1.1.5b}}%
\hyperlabel{ssub:exercise-1.1.5-b}
Show that more than a quarter of the symbols are sentence symbols.
\textit{Suggestion}: Apply induction to show that the number of sentence
symbols is $k + 1$.
symbols is of the form $k + 1$.
\code*{Enderton.Logic.Chapter\_1}
{Enderton.Logic.Chapter\_1.exercise\_1\_1\_5\_b}
\begin{proof}
TODO
\end{proof}
\subsection{\sorry{Exercise 1.1.6}}%
\hyperlabel{sub:exercise-1.1.6}
Let $\phi$ be a \nameref{ref:well-formed-formula}.
By \nameref{sub:exercise-1.1.3}, the number of sentence symbols of $\phi$ is
$k + 1$, where $k$ is the number of places at which binary connective
symbols occur in $\phi$.
By \nameref{sub:parentheses-count}, the number of parentheses in $\phi$ is
$2k$.
Thus $\phi$ has length $(k + 1) + k + 2k = 4k + 1$.
But $$\frac{k + 1}{4k + 1} > \frac{k + 1}{4k + 4} = \frac{1}{4}.$$
Hence more than a quarter of the symbols of $\phi$ are sentence symbols.
Suppose that $\alpha$ is a wff not containing the negation symbol $\neg$.
\begin{enumerate}[(a)]
\item Show that the length of $\alpha$ (i.e., the number of symbols in the
string) is odd.
\item Show that more than a quarter of the symbols are sentence symbols.
\end{enumerate}
\begin{proof}
TODO
\end{proof}
\end{document}

View File

@ -1,6 +1,9 @@
import Common.Logic.Basic
import Common.Nat.Basic
import Mathlib.Algebra.Parity
import Mathlib.Data.Nat.Basic
import Mathlib.Tactic.NormNum
import Mathlib.Tactic.Ring
/-! # Enderton.Logic.Chapter_1
@ -23,7 +26,7 @@ inductive Wff where
namespace Wff
/--
Returns the length of the expression, including symbols.
Returns the length of the expression, i.e. a count of all symbols..
-/
def length : Wff →
| Wff.SS _ => 1
@ -34,7 +37,7 @@ def length : Wff →
| Wff.Iff e₁ e₂ => length e₁ + length e₂ + 3
/--
Every well-formed formula has a positive length.
Every `Wff` has a positive length.
-/
theorem length_gt_zero (φ : Wff)
: length φ > 0 := by
@ -47,16 +50,122 @@ theorem length_gt_zero (φ : Wff)
| Cond _ _
| Iff _ _ => simp
/--
The number of sentence symbols found in the provided `Wff`.
-/
def sentenceSymbolCount : Wff →
| Wff.SS _ => 1
| Wff.Not e => sentenceSymbolCount e
| Wff.And e₁ e₂
| Wff.Or e₁ e₂
| Wff.Cond e₁ e₂
| Wff.Iff e₁ e₂ => sentenceSymbolCount e₁ + sentenceSymbolCount e₂
/--
The number of sentential connective symbols found in the provided `Wff`.
-/
def sententialSymbolCount : Wff →
| Wff.SS _ => 0
| Wff.Not e => sententialSymbolCount e + 1
| Wff.And e₁ e₂
| Wff.Or e₁ e₂
| Wff.Cond e₁ e₂
| Wff.Iff e₁ e₂ => sententialSymbolCount e₁ + sententialSymbolCount e₂ + 1
/--
The number of binary connective symbols found in the provided `Wff`.
-/
def binarySymbolCount : Wff →
| Wff.SS _ => 0
| Wff.Not e => binarySymbolCount e
| Wff.And e₁ e₂
| Wff.Or e₁ e₂
| Wff.Cond e₁ e₂
| Wff.Iff e₁ e₂ => binarySymbolCount e₁ + binarySymbolCount e₂ + 1
/--
The number of parentheses found in the provided `Wff`.
-/
def parenCount : Wff →
| Wff.SS _ => 0
| Wff.Not e => 2 + parenCount e
| Wff.And e₁ e₂
| Wff.Or e₁ e₂
| Wff.Cond e₁ e₂
| Wff.Iff e₁ e₂ => 2 + parenCount e₁ + parenCount e₂
/--
Whether or not the `Wff` contains a `¬`.
-/
def hasNotSymbol : Wff → Prop
| Wff.SS _ => False
| Wff.Not _ => True
| Wff.And e₁ e₂
| Wff.Or e₁ e₂
| Wff.Cond e₁ e₂
| Wff.Iff e₁ e₂ => hasNotSymbol e₁ hasNotSymbol e₂
/--
If a `Wff` does not contain the `¬` symbol, it has the same number of sentential
connective symbols as it does binary connective symbols. In other words, the
negation symbol is the only non-binary sentential connective.
-/
lemma no_neg_sentential_count_eq_binary_count {φ : Wff} (h : ¬φ.hasNotSymbol)
: φ.sententialSymbolCount = φ.binarySymbolCount := by
sorry
/-- #### Parentheses Count
Let `φ` be a well-formed formula and `c` be the number of places at which a
sentential connective symbol exists. Then there is `2c` parentheses in `φ`.
-/
theorem paren_count_double_sentential_count (φ : Wff)
: φ.parenCount = 2 * φ.sententialSymbolCount := by
induction φ with
| SS _ =>
unfold parenCount sententialSymbolCount
simp
| Not e ih =>
unfold parenCount sententialSymbolCount
rw [ih]
ring
| And e₁ e₂ ih₁ ih₂
| Or e₁ e₂ ih₁ ih₂
| Cond e₁ e₂ ih₁ ih₂
| Iff e₁ e₂ ih₁ ih₂ =>
unfold parenCount sententialSymbolCount
rw [ih₁, ih₂]
ring
/--
The length of a `Wff` corresponds to the summation of sentence symbols,
sentential connective symbols, and parentheses.
-/
theorem length_eq_sum_symbol_count (φ : Wff)
: φ.length = φ.sentenceSymbolCount +
φ.sententialSymbolCount +
φ.parenCount := by
induction φ with
| SS _ =>
unfold length sentenceSymbolCount sententialSymbolCount parenCount
simp
| Not e ih =>
unfold length sentenceSymbolCount sententialSymbolCount parenCount
rw [ih]
ac_rfl
| And e₁ e₂ ih₁ ih₂
| Or e₁ e₂ ih₁ ih₂
| Cond e₁ e₂ ih₁ ih₂
| Iff e₁ e₂ ih₁ ih₂ =>
unfold length sentenceSymbolCount sententialSymbolCount parenCount
rw [ih₁, ih₂]
ac_rfl
end Wff
/-! #### Exercise 1.1.2
Show that there are no wffs of length `2`, `3`, or `6`, but that any other
positive length is possible.
/--
An enumeration of values `m` and `n` can take on in equation `m + n = 3`.
-/
section Exercise_1_1_2
private lemma eq_3_by_cases (m n : ) (h : m + n = 3)
: m = 0 ∧ n = 3
m = 1 ∧ n = 2
@ -93,10 +202,16 @@ private lemma eq_3_by_cases (m n : ) (h : m + n = 3)
right; right; right
exact ⟨m_eq_3, h⟩
/-! #### Exercise 1.1.2
Show that there are no wffs of length `2`, `3`, or `6`, but that any other
positive length is possible.
-/
theorem exercise_1_1_2_i (φ : Wff)
: φ.length ≠ 2 ∧ φ.length ≠ 3 ∧ φ.length ≠ 6 := by
induction φ with
| SS c =>
| SS _ =>
unfold Wff.length
simp
| Not e ih =>
@ -140,45 +255,95 @@ theorem exercise_1_1_2_i (φ : Wff)
intro h₃
exact absurd h₃.left ih₁.right.left
theorem exercise_1_1_2_ii (n : ) (h : n ≠ 2 ∧ n ≠ 3 ∧ n ≠ 6)
theorem exercise_1_1_2_ii (n : ) (h : n ∈ Set.univ \ {2, 3, 6})
: ∃ φ : Wff, φ.length = n := by
let φ₁ := Wff.SS 1
let φ₂ := Wff.And φ₁ (Wff.SS 2)
let φ₃ := Wff.And φ₂ (Wff.SS 3)
sorry
end Exercise_1_1_2
/-! #### Exercise 1.1.3
/-- #### Exercise 1.1.3
Let `α` be a wff; let `c` be the number of places at which binary connective
symbols (`∧`, ``, `→`, `↔`) occur in `α`; let `s` be the number of places at
which sentence symbols occur in `α`. (For example, if `α` is `(A → (¬ A))` then
`c = 1` and `s = 2`.) Show by using the induction principle that `s = c + 1`.
-/
section Exercise_1_1_3
private def binary_symbol_count : Wff →
| Wff.SS _ => 0
| Wff.Not e => binary_symbol_count e
| Wff.And e₁ e₂
| Wff.Or e₁ e₂
| Wff.Cond e₁ e₂
| Wff.Iff e₁ e₂ => binary_symbol_count e₁ + binary_symbol_count e₂ + 1
private def sentence_symbol_count : Wff →
| Wff.SS _ => 1
| Wff.Not e => sentence_symbol_count e
| Wff.And e₁ e₂
| Wff.Or e₁ e₂
| Wff.Cond e₁ e₂
| Wff.Iff e₁ e₂ => sentence_symbol_count e₁ + sentence_symbol_count e₂
theorem exercise_1_1_3 (φ : Wff)
: sentence_symbol_count φ = binary_symbol_count φ + 1 := by
sorry
: φ.sentenceSymbolCount = φ.binarySymbolCount + 1 := by
induction φ with
| SS _ =>
unfold Wff.sentenceSymbolCount Wff.binarySymbolCount
simp
| Not e ih =>
unfold Wff.sentenceSymbolCount Wff.binarySymbolCount
exact ih
| And e₁ e₂ ih₁ ih₂
| Or e₁ e₂ ih₁ ih₂
| Cond e₁ e₂ ih₁ ih₂
| Iff e₁ e₂ ih₁ ih₂ =>
unfold Wff.sentenceSymbolCount Wff.binarySymbolCount
rw [ih₁, ih₂]
ring
end Exercise_1_1_3
/-- #### Exercise 1.1.5 (a)
Suppose that `α` is a wff not containing the negation symbol `¬`. Show that the
length of `α` (i.e., the number of symbols in the string) is odd.
*Suggestion*: Apply induction to show that the length is of the form `4k + 1`.
-/
theorem exercise_1_1_5_a (α : Wff) (hα : ¬α.hasNotSymbol)
: Odd α.length := by
suffices ∃ k : , α.length = 4 * k + 1 by
have ⟨k, hk⟩ := this
unfold Odd
exact ⟨2 * k, by rw [hk, ← mul_assoc]; norm_num⟩
induction α with
| SS _ =>
refine ⟨0, ?_⟩
unfold Wff.length
simp
| Not e _ =>
unfold Wff.hasNotSymbol at hα
exfalso
exact hα trivial
| And e₁ e₂ ih₁ ih₂
| Or e₁ e₂ ih₁ ih₂
| Cond e₁ e₂ ih₁ ih₂
| Iff e₁ e₂ ih₁ ih₂ =>
unfold Wff.hasNotSymbol at hα
rw [not_or_de_morgan] at hα
have ⟨k₁, hk₁⟩ := ih₁ hα.left
have ⟨k₂, hk₂⟩ := ih₂ hα.right
refine ⟨k₁ + k₂ + 1, ?_⟩
unfold Wff.length
rw [hk₁, hk₂]
ring
/-- #### Exercise 1.1.5 (b)
Suppose that `α` is a wff not containing the negation symbol `¬`. Show that more
than a quarter of the symbols are sentence symbols.
*Suggestion*: Apply induction to show that the number of sentence symbols is
`k + 1`.
-/
theorem exercise_1_1_5_b (α : Wff) (hα : ¬α.hasNotSymbol)
: α.sentenceSymbolCount > α.length / 4 := by
have h₁ := α.sentenceSymbolCount
have h₂ := α.sententialSymbolCount
have h₃ := α.parenCount
rw [
α.length_eq_sum_symbol_count,
Wff.paren_count_double_sentential_count α,
Wff.no_neg_sentential_count_eq_binary_count hα,
exercise_1_1_3 α
]
generalize Wff.binarySymbolCount α = k
calc k + 1
_ = 4 * (k + 1) / 4 := Eq.symm $ Nat.mul_div_cancel_left (k + 1) (by simp)
_ = (k + 4 + k + 2 * k) / 4 := by ring_nf
_ > (k + 1 + k + 2 * k) / 4 := by sorry
end Enderton.Logic.Chapter_1

View File

@ -1,5 +1,6 @@
import Bookshelf.Enderton.Set.Chapter_1
import Bookshelf.Enderton.Set.Chapter_2
import Bookshelf.Enderton.Set.Chapter_3
import Bookshelf.Enderton.Set.Chapter_4
import Bookshelf.Enderton.Set.OrderedPair
import Bookshelf.Enderton.Set.Relation